Supplement to Set Theory
Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory (ZF)
Axioms of ZF
Extensionality:
∀x∀y[∀z(z∈x↔z∈y)→x=y]
This axiom asserts that when sets x and y have the same members, they are the same set.
The next axiom asserts the existence of the empty set:
Null Set:
∃x¬∃y(y∈x)
Since it is provable from this axiom and the previous axiom that there is a unique such set, we may introduce the notation ‘∅’ to denote it.
The next axiom asserts that given any sets x and y, there exists a pair set of x and y, i.e., a set which has only x and y as members:
Pairs:
∀x∀y∃z∀w(w∈z↔w=x∨w=y)
Since it is provable that there is a unique pair set for each given x and y, we introduce the notation ‘{x,y}’ to denote it. In the particular case when x=y, the axiom asserts the existence of the singleton {x}, namely the set having x as its unique member.
The next axiom asserts that for any set x, there is a set y which contains as members all those sets whose members are also elements of x, i.e., y contains all of the subsets of x:
Power Set:
∀x∃y∀z[z∈y↔∀w(w∈z→w∈x)]
Since every set provably has a unique ‘power set’, we introduce the notation ‘P(x)’ to denote it. Note also that we may define the notion x is a subset of y (‘x⊆y’) as: ∀z(z∈x→z∈y). Then we may simplify the statement of the Power Set Axiom as follows:
∀x∃y∀z(z∈y↔z⊆x)
The next axiom asserts that for any given set x, there is a set y which has as members all of the members of all of the members of x:
Unions:
∀x∃y∀z[z∈y↔∃w(w∈x∧z∈w)]
Since it is provable that there is a unique ‘union’ of any set x, we introduce the notation ‘⋃x’ to denote it.
The next axiom asserts the existence of an infinite set, i.e., a set with an infinite number of members:
Infinity:
∃x[∅∈x∧∀y(y∈x→⋃{y,{y}}∈x)]
We may think of this as follows. Let us define the union of x and y (‘x∪y’) as the union of the pair set of x and y, i.e., as ⋃{x,y}. Then the Axiom of Infinity asserts that there is a set x which contains ∅ as a member and which is such that whenever a set y is a member of x, then y∪{y} is also a member of x. Consequently, this axiom guarantees the existence of a set of the following form:
{∅,{∅},{∅,{∅}},{∅,{∅},{∅,{∅}}},…}
Notice that the second element, {∅}, is in this set because (1) the fact that ∅ is in the set implies that ∅∪{∅} is in the set and (2) ∅∪{∅} just is {∅}. Similarly, the third element, {∅,{∅}}, is in this set because (1) the fact that {∅} is in the set implies that {∅}∪{{∅}} is in the set and (2) {∅}∪{{∅}} just is {∅,{∅}}. And so forth.
Next is the Separation Schema, which is a formula-pattern that uses a metavariable (in this case ψ) to describe an infinite list of axioms – one axiom for each formula of the language of set theory with at least a free variable. Every instance of the Separation Schema asserts the existence of a set that contains the elements of a given set w that satisfy a certain condition, which is given by a formula ψ. That is, suppose that ψ(x,u1,…,uk) is a formula of the language of set theory that has x free and may or may not have u1,…,uk free. Then the Separation Schema for the condition ψ asserts:
Separation:
∀u1…∀uk[∀w∃v∀r(r∈v↔r∈w∧ψ(r,u1,…,uk))]
In other words, given sets w and u1,…,uk, there exists a set v which has as members precisely the members r of w which satisfy the formula ψ(r,u1,…,uk).
Next is the Replacement Schema, which is also a formula-pattern that uses a metavariable (in this case ϕ) to describe an infinite list of axioms -- one axiom for each formula of the language of set theory with at least two free variables. Suppose that ϕ(x,y,u1,…,uk) is a formula with x and y free, and in which u1,…uk may or may not be free. Then the instance of the Replacement Schema given by ϕ(x,y,u1,…,uk) is the following axiom:
Replacement:
∀u1…∀uk[∀x∃!yϕ(x,y,u1,…uk)→
∀w∃v∀r(r∈v↔∃s(s∈w∧ϕ(s,r,u1,…uk)))]
In other words, if we know that ϕ is a functional formula (which relates each set x to a unique set y), then if we are given a set w, we can form a new set v as follows: collect all of the sets to which the members of w are uniquely related by ϕ.
Note that the Replacement Schema can take you ‘out of’ the set w when forming the set v. The elements of v need not be elements of w. By contrast, the Separation Schema of Zermelo only yields subsets of the given set w.
The final axiom asserts that every set is ‘well-founded’:
Regularity:
∀x[x≠∅→∃y(y∈x∧∀z(z∈x→¬(z∈y)))]
A member y of a set x with this property is called a ‘minimal’ element. This axiom rules out the existence of circular chains of sets (e.g., such as x∈y∧y∈z∧z∈x) as well as infinitely descending chains of sets (such as … x3∈x2∈x1∈x0).